A) Fiber Optics will change
the face of the Internet
The imminent use of fiber
optic cable to speed data across the internet is expected to dramatically
increase both the volume of, and rate at which, information can be sent
and received.1 This in turn is expected to significantly enhance
the quality and range of services that can be provided to (or by) a casual
user, at little or no cost. Thus it not unforeseeable that in short
time both common man and corporate giant will be able to send and receive
live and pre-recorded audio-video transmissions across the Internet and
into each others homes.2 How will this audio-visual cyber-revolution
affect the application of defamation law, as applied to Internet communications?
To answer this question, it is first necessary to trace the tort's procedural
evolution.
B) The old system
Historically, the distinction
between slander and libel was relatively easy: if the defamatory communication
was spoken or by conveyed by gesture, it was a slander; if it was written,
drawn or printed, it was a libel.3
This distinction was often important:
In order to obtain a damages in a suit for slander, the plaintiff had to
make a specific showing of how his or her reputation had been harmed (there
are enumerated content-based exceptions to this requirement).4 Proving
this harm was (and is) not always an easy task. However, in an action
for libel, harm was presumed.5 Therefore, if the plaintiff
was unable to demonstrate specific harm, this distinction, between libel
and slander, would have been dispositive as to whether or not the plaintiff
was financially compensated for his or her reputational loss -- no small
matter.
C) The Modern System
The historical distinction between
slander and libel was somewhat diminished following two modern Supreme
Court cases.
In Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc.,
the Supreme Court (expressing First Amendment concerns that juries might
be arbitrarily punishing unpopular opinion in the absence of actual damages),
held that the states could no longer permit the recovery of presumed damages
when liability was not based upon a showing of a knowledge of falsity or
a reckless disregard of the truth (actual malice).6
Then, in Dun & Bradstreet
v. Greenmoss Builders, the court backtracked slightly, allowing presumed
damages (even absent a showing of actual malice) in cases involving non-public
figures, where the burden of demonstrating actual damages are great, serious
harm is all but certain, and the communication at issue is "speech of no
public concern."7
In light of these cases,
some may mistaken believe that the distinction has lost its bite.
However, consider: First, the field of defamation cases involving actual
malice is significant, and therefore the distinction should still be treated
as very relevant. Second, although the court in Dun & Bradstreet
announced an exception for speech involving "no matters of public concern,"
Justice Brennan contends (in a dissenting opinion) that the plurality failed
to adequately define the parameters of such speech, and thus it remains
somewhat of an open question as to the scope of its reach.8
Thus, once again, in such aforementioned
cases where the plaintiff is unable to demonstrate actual harm, this distinction,
between libel and slander, may yet once again prove dispositive as to whether
or not the plaintiff's efforts to secure damages succeeds or fails.
C) Enter broadcasting:
Libel or slander?
Before these two cases
were decided, the courts had to wrestle with a new and unique medium, both
persuasive and pervasive: broadcasting -- a medium whose pre-dominant means
of communication (in both radio and television) is speech. Strict
application of the old rules, would, on its face, seem to suggest that
slander provides the appropriate standard for broadcasting; after all,
its dominant means of communications is speech. However, many courts
(and legislatures) thought otherwise, concluding that such a strict application
of the old rules would be grossly out of step with the original purposes
for making the distinction (which we will discuss shortly). To illustrate:
it is now perfectly reasonable to presume that a broadcasted oral defamation
might reach an audience as great as, if not greater than, one accessible
to a pervasive printed medium, such as a newspaper. And with the
advent of modern recording devices, a broadcasted defamation could, like
a libel, assume a semi-permanent and tangible form (capable of re-offending).
Accordingly, many states now treat broadcasting as libel. However,
this trend is not universal. Other states (such as California), have
resolved that broadcasting be treated as slander.9 Thus the debate
over broadcasting continues.
D) Early Internet defamation:
Libel is consistent with historical treatment
So along comes the Internet,
a media within which, at the time of this writing, all (or almost all)
of the defamation therein involves the written (as opposed to the spoken)
word. Thus, unlike broadcasting, the old rules (focusing on the written/spoken
distinction) have been easily applied with little or no objection: defamation
on the Internet is (or at least, always has been) litigated as libel.
Not only might this help explain why no court or scholarship has addressed
this issue, it may also suggest why lawyers have, to date, simply litigated
cyber-defamation as libel, without giving the matter much thought.
However, that's all about to change....
E) Audio-visual cyber-defamation:
Libel or slander?
No clear answer
As mentioned earlier, the
imminent application of fiber-optic cable as the carrier of Internet communications
is expected to revolutionize the medium. As a result, it is quite
foreseeable that bulletin boards and chat rooms will take on a predominantly
audio-visual nature, as opposed to a printed one; instead of "Joe Citizen's"
letter and graphic oriented homepage, perhaps we'll get Joe Citizen delivering
much of the site's communications himself (it would be easier than typing,
and may even him the psychological satisfaction of feeling self-important).
In addition, unlike traditional
television, not only will the number of outlets be potentially limitless,
but also the overhead involved in setting up and sending such transmissions
will be close to negligible.10 Therefore, it is not unforeseeable
that the propensity for audio-visual Internet defamation will skyrocket,
and the courts may not know how to classify it.
Therefore, as technology
moves the Internet's nature, as a whole, closer to broadcasting, the courts
will be forced to decide whether it be wise to treat it as if it were.
Which brings us back to our question.... whether the courts should treat
audio-visual cyber-defamation as libel, slander, both, or something new.
Once again, the determination arrived at may prove dispositive at to whether
a plaintiff's quest for damages fails or succeeds.
II. BACKGROUND: WHY WE DISTINGUISH
LIBEL FROM SLANDER:
The logical first step in deciding
how to treat audio-visual cyber-defamation is to inquire as to why the
courts initially distinguished slander from libel (admitting that many
authorities are divided or uncertain on this question).
One suggestion has been
that the distinction arose at a time when relatively few people could read,
and thus written communications were perceived as being more credible.11
Likewise, people may have believed that a writing was more likely than
a verbal utterance to have been the product of careful deliberation, again
enhancing its perceived credibility.12
A second possibility was
that a libel could be communicated to a larger audience than a slander,
thereby increasing the likelihood of greater reputational harm.13
In addition, unlike a slander (which ceases to exist after being spoken)
a single libelous statement has the propensity to re-offend countless times
(due to its semi-permanent form).14
A third and related reason
is that these disparities in credibility and audience size may have convinced
the courts (or at least the Star Chamber) that libels were more likely
to incite breaches of the peace.15 Avoiding breaches of the peace
was itself a major premise for creating the two torts, each of which seek
to provide a lawful forum in which plaintiffs can seek restitution for:
1) injuries to a plaintiff's reputation, 2) resulting financial loss, and
3) emotional distress suffered.16
Armed with these theories,
we can now inquire as to the appropriate standard for audio-visual cyber-defamation.
This analysis should suggest that concocting a blanket classification for
the Internet as a medium would be out of step with the original purposes
for the differing torts.
III. DO THE ORIGINAL PURPOSES
OF THE LIBEL/SLANDER
DISTINCTION SUGGEST TREATING
AUDIO-VISUAL DEFAMATION ON
THE INTERNET THE SAME AS AUDIO-VISUAL
DEFAMATION ON
TELEVISION?
Because judges and legislators
may be inclined to look to the law's treatment of broadcasting for guidance
on how to classify audio-visual cyber-defamation, it seems appropriate
to compare the Internet and broadcasting alongside each other in light
of the original purposes for the libel/slander distinction. The analysis
that follows treats broadcasting as if it is libel, and assumes, unless
otherwise noted, that the communications at issue are or were available
to a general public.
REASON # 1: CREDIBILITY
Do viewers attribute sufficient
credibility to the Internet, so as to justify a court in treating all audio-visual
defamation as libel?
A) On the Internet, it is
the speaker, not the medium,
that counts:
Broadcasting's "...wide
dissemination...together with its prestige and potential effect upon the
public mind as a standardized means of publication is such that many people
tend automatically to accept it as conveying the truth, and as such puts
the broadcaster on the same footing as the publisher of a newspaper."17
Can the same be said of
the Internet?
It would be quite reasonable
to assume as much if the alleged defamation was communicated on the "CBS
Evening Cyber-Cast" or National Public Radio's on-line audio-clips.
In light of both the potential audience, on one hand, and the prestige
of the sources, an excellent argument could be made that if a court would
hold the same to be libel if broadcasted, then it should also do the same
in this context.
On the other hand, it might be
questionable wisdom indeed to rely on information received from one of
the millions of unfamiliar and anonymous cyber-declarants communicating
through this wide-open medium. Thus, not only might the credibility
of the speaker be suspect, the prestige of the medium would be non-existent.
After all, if the medium is one that is available to just about anyone,
the effect on the public mind should be negligible. Thus, to say
one heard such and such on the internet, by itself, is no more or less
prestigious or credible than if the same message was communicated on a
public street corner (where the title of the Brooklyn Bridge is rumored
to pass quite often).
Exacerbating this credibility
gap between the "establishment" sites and those which are unfamiliar, are
the viewers not irrational perceptions that it is far less likely that
internet communications (as a class) are being screened by trained editors
to ensure minimal safeguards against the dissemination of false statements.18
In fact, where interactive Internet communications are a predominant feature
of the website (as is the case in Internet chat rooms and bulletin boards),
screening may be financially impossible, in light of the sheer volume of
Internet traffic. In contrast, broadcast sources exclusively control
what is disseminated to the public, and thus can exercise greater control.
Moreover, lest you forget
the effects potential litigation might have on a speaker, consider also
that it is often much easier, by and large, to identify the source of a
broadcasted audio-visual defamation, as compared to the same when communicated
on the Internet. Broadcasting's stations and producers are not only
easily identifiable, but the majority of them are backed by relatively
deep pockets (unlike many Internet communicators). These deep pockets
may very well provide not only the means to guard against the unintentional
issuance defamatory statements, but also the incentives.19
In contrast, it is no secret
that locating the source of an Internet communication may prove difficult
or impossible. Moreover, even if identified, because of the negligible
cost involved in Internet communications, it is quite possible that the
defendant might be, for all intents and purposes, financially judgment-proof.20
The public may, in turn, take these economic considerations into account
when assessing credibility.
In sum, it is reasonable
to assert that information conveyed by means of broadcasting is, by and
large, more likely to have been the product of more careful deliberations
than much of that conveyed over the internet, a medium which, alone and
of itself, carries no instant credibility.
Therefore, in the context
of the Internet, the credibility of the speaker (and not the medium) should
be weighed when determining whether or not a particular instance of cyber-defamation
should be treated as libel or slander.
B) The speaker's credibility
should also be assessed, in light of its context
Should it make a difference
whether or not the defamatory message was conveyed over a passive pre-recorded
web site, as opposed to a live audio-visual chat room?
For guidance, I recommend
the California Supreme Court's "totality of the circumstances" test.
As noted by that tribunal: "What constitutes a statement of fact in one
context may be treated as a statement of opinion in another, in light of
the nature and content of the communication taken as a whole. Thus,
where potentially defamatory statements are published in a public debate,
a heated labor dispute, or in another setting in which the audience may
anticipate efforts by the parties to persuade others to their positions
by use of epithets, fiery rhetoric or hyperbole, language which generally
might be considered as statements of fact may well assume the character
of statements of opinion."21
Thus, a disparagement made in
the middle of a passionate on-going audio-visual chat room conversation
might be more suggestive of a slander than one pre-recorded and made available
on a passive website by the site's author (the latter being more likely
the product of deliberate reflection rather than spontaneity).
Furthermore, there is separate
precedent suggesting that when making such a credibility assessment, the
factfinder might also consider the speaker's apparent state of mind --
was he speaking sarcastically, off the cuff, in the heat of passion, under
the influence, and so forth (all of which may be readily discernable, in
a case of alleged audio-visual defamation). Georgia's Court of Appeals
has argued that such factors may suggest less careful deliberation, and
therefore "a publication may be libelous when, if spoken orally, it would
not be slanderous."22
Of course, common sense acknowledges
that a defamation posted within a live chat room conversation may have
been carefully planned in advance, and such is an appropriate question
for the factfinder; I only mean to suggest that careful deliberation is
less likely in such a forum.
Thus, the modality of an
Internet site should be separately considered when trying to classify the
cyber-tort as libel or slander.
C) Did or should the speaker
have known that the conversation might later be re-accessed?
Reconsider for a moment
a few other reasons why libel is deemed more credible than most slanders.
For most, writing takes longer
to transcribe and compose than speech, and there is usually some unspecified
time between a writing's composition and its delivery (allowing yet more
time for reconsideration of the message). Furthermore, it might be
harder to convincingly deny the specific contents of a publicly disseminated
and tangible writing, than a forever gone conversation, now regretted.
Thus, having exercised greater care in the message's composition, the message
(even if spoken) may come across as more persuasive. Accordingly,
the perception of a libel as being the product of careful deliberation
may nonetheless hold some weight, (despite the modern rise in literacy
rates. An indirect correlation is suggested). But can the same
be said about messages conveyed over the Internet in an on-going, live
cyber-communication?
Many of the above-mentioned
considerations would not apply in such a context. In addition, unless
a communication is saved, it will permanently dissipate once the computer's
power is cut off, calling into question any labeling of such speech as
semi-permanent. This being the case, if a speaker has no reason to
believe that a given communication is being saved, it may not be unrealistic
to suppose that the conversation may often be afforded no greater precautions
than those commonly exercised in day-to-day speech, further calling into
question any suggestion of any enhanced credibility, actual or perceived.
And although I know of
no case directly suggesting as much, could the inquiry into careful deliberation
also implicitly speak to perceived culpability, just as pre-meditated homicide
(the product of careful deliberation) is treated more severely than second-degree
homicide (committed in the heat of spontaneous passion)?
Thus, it may not be enough
to merely inquire as to whether or not the cyber-communication was saved.
Perhaps we should also inquire as to the quality of the speaker's deliberations,
during, and after the words were spoken. In doing so, we might inquire
as to: Who saved the communications? Did the defendant know or have
reason to inquire as to whether the communications were being saved?
Were the communications made in the presence of casual friends, or others
whose relationship to the speaker is such as to naturally provoke careful
deliberations (such as officer addressing a board of trustees)? When
was the decision to save the communications made? Beforehand?
Immediately after the defamatory utterance? After subsequent communications
within the same conversation, but for reasons unrelated to the earlier
defamatory statements? Was the defamatory message later erased or
distributed? Why, when and in what context? Was the saved material
available for others to peruse? If the speaker later learned that
his or her communication was saved without the speaker's knowledge, did
the speaker attempt to, or have the means to, destroy the copy? These
considerations may speak to whether or not the defamatory utterance should
be treated as spontaneous or well thought out, and may hint as to how they
may have been perceived by most viewers. Thus, when considering how
to classify the tort, factors such as those above (correlating semi-permanency
with credibility), might appropriately be considered.
Reason #2: LARGER AUDIENCES & PERMANENCE
A) Libel's presumption of
damages was chiefly concerned
with actual mass distribution
One of the more commonly
cited reasons for presuming damages in a libel action is that libels tend
to (or at least, have a greater propensity to) reach larger audiences than
might otherwise be expected of a comparable slander. This seems to
be the most rational justification for the presumption of damages in light
of the tort's history.
My case in point: the tort
of libel was not recognized at common law until immediately after the advent
of the printing press.23 Prior to that time, an aggrieved plaintiff
could only bring suit for slander.24 The written word, however, was
not new to that era, but in fact had been part of our collective culture
for thousands of years. This suggests that the mere fact that a defamation
took place in the context of a writing should not necessarily warrant the
conclusion that it is or was more dangerous (despite its assuming a semi-permanency,
by virtue of its paper medium), otherwise the libel/slander distinction
logically should have been recognized long before the printing press.
This finding, in turn, not only diminishes the relative weight of the earlier
credibility-based considerations for the libel/slander distinction, but
more importantly suggests that the court's subsequent blind adherence to
the writing vs. speech dividing line was long off the mark.
So what should we make
of that prior case law which found a libel where a written or transcripted
defamation delivered orally (despite the fact that the written or transcripted
version was witnessed by none)?25 Putting any credibility-based justifications
aside (which may or may not be sufficient to justify the outcome) is potential
distribution enough? Or must it actually be distributed? Although
prior precedent clearly suggests that no distribution is necessary, in
light of the timing of libel's advent as a tort (alongside the rise of
the printing press), it seems clear that potential distribution alone should
be insufficient for a presumption of damages. After all, how could
any rational court conclude that the plaintiff's presumption of damages
should turn upon the existence or non-existence of a document that never
saw the light of day and may no longer exist? That's absurd!
More likely, the presumption
of damages was targeted toward actual mass distribution (printing presses
being available to few then), serving predominantly as a means of approximating
reputational damage, otherwise very difficult to ascertain (deposing the
entire city, being a slight administrative inconvenience).
B) Audience size & the
relevance of reputational
cyber-communities
If we were to accept the
above thesis (that the presumption of damages was primarily targeted toward
actual mass distribution; the administrative impracticalities involved
in demonstrating actual harm in such a case are prohibitive; and the harm
resulting from such a mass distribution can be presumed in light of the
judgement and history of our collective life experiences), then we should
compare the three mediums -- newspaper, broadcasting, and the Internet
-- for their relative effects, in light of those three criteria.
Unlike traditional defamation
cases involving local broadcasters and newspapers, is it more foreseeable
that a given defamatory statement expressed on one of an innumerable sea
of websites may reach few, if any, of those who knew of, or should have
reasonably been expected to have otherwise later learned of, the plaintiff
or the plaintiff's reputation. Moreover, if no reputational harm
can be reasonably inferred in a given context, (and if the torts of libel
and slander are premised on redressing reputational harm; they are), then
presuming such harm appears inequitable and misguided.26
Certainly, a slanderous statement
announced before a gathering of 100 of the plaintiff's close associates
would probably prove more damaging than a web site that projects a defamatory
message, gets 10 hits, and is subsequently removed. As noted by Florida's
Supreme Court in Florida Star v. B.J.F. "...an individual who maliciously
spreads word of the identity of a rape victim ... to persons who live near,
or work with, the victim may have consequences equally devastating as the
exposure of her name to a large number of strangers." Yet to punish
the speaker of the defamatory internet statements (assuming that the defendant
could prove there were only 10 hits) and not the author of the live slander
(assuming that the victim is unable to demonstrate actual damages) is a
dubious proposition indeed, particularly if the 10 hits were from parties
outside of the defamed plaintiff's professional and community circles,
(and if the third parties did not know of nor have reason to know of the
plaintiff, at present or in anticipated future dealings).27 A new
means of approximation is needed.
C) Estimating audience
size: Identifying a reputational
cyber-community
Assuming that it is not
possible to identify and depose the totality of those viewing a given internet
communication (an assumption that, in reality, should not be made until
the facts of a particular case suggest as much), I would suggest that a
court adopt the following means of approximating reputational damage:
Is the internet site, within
which the defamatory statement is communicated, the type of site that a
reasonable factfinder might expect to be visited by a significant number
third parties who knew of (or would reasonably have been expected to have
later learned of) the plaintiff or his reputation? (And if so, could
a reasonable factfinder conclude that the offending web site is, as a whole,
sufficiently credible so as to allow a reasonable member of the plaintiff's
reputational community to conclude that the defamatory contents, as communicated
in that particular context, may be true?)
In order to determine whether
or not a web sight is one likely to be visited be third parties having
knowledge of the plaintiff's reputation, we must first define the relevant
third party "communities."28 For example, an anthropologist may be
a relatively unknown persona within his or her geographical community,
yet may command instant recognition and influence among anthropologists
worldwide (an example of what I might fancy, a "geographically dispersed
cyber-community"). Thus, a statement disparaging the anthropologist's
research may cause no little or no damage if uttered in one context (small-town
newspaper), and be particularly harmful if uttered in another (Anthropology.com).
Once the plaintiff has
identified those communities whose membership could reasonably be expected
to know of the plaintiff or the plaintiff's reputation, the plaintiff should
proceed to identify those other communities, whose membership might reasonably
be expected to both 1) later form an opinion regarding the plaintiff's
reputation, and 2) likely recall and associate the defamatory message with
the aggrieved plaintiff at a time when the their opinions might reasonably
be expected to be form. This second step helps to ensure that the
defendant is held responsible for a realistic approximation of the damages
actually caused, and not all of those conceivably imagined (no matter how
unlikely).29
The final step should be
to ask whether or not the web page displaying the offending message is
of such a character to have likely attracted those classes of people.
If, for example, the message was posted on a web site titled "Negligent
Techniques in Anthropology," a factfinder might reasonably conclude that
this site would likely be visited by a substantial number of people with
similar interests, who, more so than the internet community as a whole,
may more reasonably be expected to have heard of (or would later have learned
of) the aggrieved anthropologist. Conversely, if the same defamatory
message was posted on a web page titled "The American Nazi Party," a reasonable
factfinder would probably conclude that few if any anthropologists would
likely have perused that site. Thus, implies that the factfinder
would also have to decide whether or not to believe the anthropologist's
unlikely testimony that several of his professional peers just happened
to be browsing the obscure Nazi website and took its message as gospel
(if they did, one might wonder if the plaintiff had a reputation subject
to damage, in the eyes of a biased beholder).
Of course, it is also possible
that the defamatory message was posted to a popular website appealing to
a general audience. Again, the factfinder might balance any testimony
of those claiming to have both known the anthropologist and visited the
website, against the statistical likelihood of such. Obviously, the
more hits a website gets, the more plausible the claim that the defamatory
message was indeed substantially viewed by members of an actual or cyber-community
bearing knowledge of the plaintiff.
E) Private Internet communications:
a clear case for slander
This section addresses
the situation wherein the cyber-defamation is communicated by means of
a private audio-visual conference viewed by a known universe of viewers
numbering no greater than that reasonably foreseeable at a live meeting
or public gathering. Here, the fact pattern parallels that of a live,
face-to-face conversation or a telephone conference call. Calling
a defamation committed within this cyber-context a libel would require
an incredible leap of logic; it is clearly a slander (spontaneity, small
& limited audience, spoken, no fixed medium of semi-permanence created
by the speaker, no prestige inherent in the medium).
Perhaps no better fact
pattern than the one above can demonstrate the grave fallacy of applying
the law of broadcast defamation unthinkingly to the internet (again, assuming
that most states would treat broadcasting as libel), as none of the awe,
power and credibility justifications many jurisdictions have relied upon
in treating broadcasting as libel are present. A presumption of damages
in such a context would not only be administratively unnecessary, but possibly
unfair to the accused.
Furthermore, even if this same
conversation was not private, but in fact, available to all who cared to
join, assuming that the viewers could later be identified (by monitoring
and tracking hits), and assuming the number of viewers were not more than
that which could be addressed in a normal conversation or public gathering
(so as to not make unconscionable an automatic designation of slander),
the analysis should not change.
Notice, that even with regards
to the least watched television program at the least desirable hour on
the least watched station, identifying all the viewers may be, for all
intents and purposes, impossible, and thus there is more support of a prima
facie case for designating such communications as libel.
Therefore, where the audio-visual
cyber-defamation is communicated by means of a audio-visual conference
viewed by a known universe of viewers numbering no greater than that reasonably
foreseeable at a live meeting or public gathering, treat the tort as a
slander.
Caveat: If these viewers,
although discernable, are dispersed and cannot be summoned to court because
of long-arm jurisdictional problems (as is not unforeseeable, in the context
of the Internet), the case for slander is, at the very least, weaker, (as
an inability to question the viewers under oath may make it more difficult
for the plaintiff to affirmatively demonstrate reputational damages).
REASON #3: ENCOURAGING A PEACEFUL
REDRESS OF GRIEVANCES
The diffusion of internet
participants, combined with (the apparent disparity in credibility and
prestige between the Internet, on one hand, and traditional media, on the
other), may suggest that those media, for the time being, remain more likely
to incite breaches of the peace than the Internet. To what extent
this is (and remains) true should probably be assessed on a case-by-case
basis, in light of changing technological circumstance, all of the aforementioned
factors, and common sense. Not much need be said on this element
for now.
Nevertheless, attention
should at least be directly briefly to the disparity in the right of reply.
Public officials and public
figures not only have greater access than most to the various high-exposure,
traditional channels of communication, but they can also more readily (by
virtue of their fame) get their messages communicated prominently on the
Internet's most highly visited sites. Thus, when these public figures
engage in cyber-defamation, the defamatory words spoken by them may prove
particularly damaging, not only because of their personal prestige, but
also because their messages are more likely to be sought out.
In contrast, individuals
rarely become true public figures by exclusive virtue of their Internet
communications (Matt Drudge, being a rare exception, and much of his publicity
coming by virtue of traditional media referencing his site). This
disparity is not particularly surprisingly when one considers the near-infinite
numbers of low-cost specialty sights and the diffusion of audience viewing.
Thus, a defamatory material conveyed on "Joe Citizen's website" is far
less likely to be read than the same posted to Oprah Winfrey's.
The point being made here:
it is less likely that "Joe Citizen" could adequately refute the defamation
posted within Oprah's website, by posting a reply on "Joe Citizen.com."30
Sadly, not all websites are created equal. Therefore, the celebrity
attached to various sites and speakers may be relevant when assessing defamation's
likelihood of inciting a breach of the peace.
IV. CONCLUSION: CYBER-DEFAMATION
SHOULD BE CLASSIFIED ON
A CASE-BY-CASE
BASIS, IN LIGHT OF THE DISTINCTION'S
ORIGINAL PURPOSES
At least one court has
suggested that oral broadcast communications could be treated as libel
on some occasions, and slander on others.31 So also it should be
for the Internet. The call for applying new, hybrid methodology to
defamation in an electronic era is by no means new to our jurisprudence
and is long overdue.32
In fact, I will concurrently
argue that a reassessment of our blind adherence to the writing vs. speech
distinction is further warranted. Long the subject of criticism and
not always in keeping with the original purposes of our affording the torts
differing treatment, one of the implicit themes of this paper has been
that a presumption of damages should be allowed only when in accordance
with the purposes, and not the mere letter, of the law. The imminent
classification debate over audio-visual cyber-defamation may be the long-awaited
vehicle for sparking this reform.
Now it is your turn, the
cyber-litigator, to apply these common law distinctions in a way that does
their policies, and your client, justice.
Libel or slander?
The final determination should be decided as a matter of law, on a case-by-case
basis.
1 David Ansen & Ray Sawhill,
Now at a Desktop Near You, Newsweek, March 15, 1999 (page unavailable on
Westlaw)
2 David Ansen & Ray Sawhill,
Now at a Desktop Near You, Newsweek, March 15, 1999 (page unavailable on
Westlaw)
3 RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS
§ 568.1 (1977)
4 T. BARTON CARTER, THE FIRST
AMENDMENT AND THE FIFTH ESTATE 696 (Fourth ed., Foundation Press, Inc.
1996).
5 John B. McCrory, Constitutional
Privilege in Libel Law, 498 PLI/Pat 53, 443 (1997).
6 Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc.
418 U.S. 323, 439 (1974)
7 Dun & Bradstreet v. Greenmoss
Builders, 472 U.S. 749, 761 (1985)
8 Ibid. at 748 (Brennan dissenting)
9 T. BARTON CARTER, THE FIRST
AMENDMENT AND THE FIFTH ESTATE 696 (fourth ed., The Foundation Press, Inc.
1996).
10 David Ansen & Ray Sawhill,
Now at a Desktop Near You, Newsweek, March 15, 1999 (page unavailable on
Westlaw)
11 T. BARTON CARTER, THE FIRST
AMENDMENT AND THE FIFTH ESTATE 696 (fourth ed., The Foundation Press, Inc.
1996).
12 Ibid. at 696
13 RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS
§ 568 cmt. d (1977)
14 RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS
§ 568 cmt. d (1977)
15 RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS
§ 568 cmt. b (1977)
16 John B. McCrory, Constitutional
Privilege in Libel Law, 498 PLI/Pat 53, 451 (1997).
17 RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS
§ 568A cmt. a (1977)
18 Michael Hadley, The Gertz
Doctrine and Internet Defamation, 84 Va. L. Rev. 477, 505
19 Ibid. at 506
20 Ibid. at 506
21 Gregory v. McDonnell Douglas
Corp., 131 Cal.Rptr. 641, 644 (1976).
22 American Broadcasting-Paramount
Theaters, Inc., et al. v. Simpson et al., 106 Ga. App. 230, 235
American Broadcasting-Paramount
Theaters, Inc., et al. v. Simpson et al., 106 Ga. App. 230, 236, citing
Landau v. Columbia Broadcasting System, Inc., 205 Misc. 357 (128 NYS 2d
254) (dramatic television presentation from script held libel) and Remington
v. Bentley, 88 FSupp. 166 (SD, NY) (defamatory remark on extemporaneous
television program held slander, applying New York law). But see Shor v.
Billingsley, 158 NYS 2d 476, holding to the contrary.
23 RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS
§ 568 cmt. a (1977)
24 RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS
§ 568 cmt. b (1977)
25 RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS
§ 568 illus. 3e, 3f (1977)
26 Lyle v. Waddle, 188 S.W.2d
770, 771 (Texas 1945)
27 Florida Star v. B.J.F. 491
U.S. 524, 540 (1989)
28 Smith v. Suburban Restaraunts,
Inc. 373 N.E.2d 215, 216 (Mass. 1978)
29 As an extreme example, if
someone made slanderous statements about you to the Australian aboriginal
bushmen, could you
honestly claim that your reputation had somehow been harmed in a way so
as to
warrant compensation?
Any such harm, present of future, is likely either nominal or non-existent.
30 Michael Hadley, The Gertz
Doctrine and Internet Defamation, 84 Va. L. Rev. 477, 494
31 Greer v. Skyway Broadcasting
Co, 256 N.C. 382, 390 (1962)
32 Kelly v. Hoffman, (Wachenfield,
J: Dissenting) 137 N.J.L. 695, 701 (1948)